NICOMACHEAN ETHICS
Book V
(A)
We have shown that both the unjust man and the unjust act are unfair or
unequal; now it is clear that there is also an intermediate between the two
unequals involved in either case. And this is the equal; for in any kind of
action in which there’s a more and a less there is also what is equal. If,
then, the unjust is unequal, just is equal, as all men suppose it to be, even
apart from argument. And since the equal is intermediate, the just will be an
intermediate. Now equality implies at least two things. The just, then, must be
both intermediate and equal and relative (i.e. for certain persons). And since
the equall intermediate it must be between certain things (which are
respectively greater and less); equal, it involves two things; qua just, it is
for certain people. The just, therefore, involves at least four terms; for the
persons for whom it is in fact just are two, and the things in which it is
manifested, the objects distributed, are two. And the same equality will exist between the persons and
between the things concerned; for as the latter the things concerned — are related [Ross ne parle pas de rapport mais de relation],
so are the former; if they are not equal, they will not have what is equal, but
this is the origin of quarrels and complaints — when either equals have and are
awarded unequal shares, or unequals equal shares. Further, this is plain from
the fact that awards should be
‘according to merit’; for all men agree that what is just in distribution
must be according to merit in some sense, though they do not all specify the
same sort of merit, but democrats identify it with the status of freeman,
supporters of oligarchy with wealth (or with noble birth), and supporters of
aristocracy with excellence.
The
just, then, is a species of the proportionate (proportion being not a property
only of the kind of number which consists of abstract units, but of number in
general). For proportion is equality of ratios, and involves four terms at
least (that discrete proportion involves four terms is plain, but so does
continuous proportion, for it uses one term as two and mentions it twice; e.g.
‘as the line A is to the line B, so is the line B to the line C’; the line B,
then, has been mentioned twice, so that if the line B be assumed twice, the
proportional terms will be four); and the just, too, involves at least four
terms, and the ratio between one pair is the same as that between the other
pair; for there is a similar distinction between the persons and between the
things. As the term A, then, is to B, so will C be to D, and therefore,
alternando, as A is to C, B will be to D. Therefore also the whole is in the
same ratio to the whole; and this coupling the distribution effects, and, if
the terms are so combined, effects justly. The conjunction, then, of the term A
with C and of B with D is hat is just in distribution, and this species of the
just is intermediate, and the unjust is what violates he proportion; for the
proportional is intermediate, and the just is proportional. (Mathematicians
call this kind of proportion geometrical; for it is in geometrical proportion
that it follows that the whole is to the whole as either part is to the
corresponding part.) This proportion is not continuous; for we cannot get a single term [Ross parle de terme unique] standing for a person and a
thing.
This,
then, is what the just is — the proportional; the unjust is what violates the
proportion. Hence one term becomes too great, the other too small, as indeed
happens in practice; for the man who acts unjustly has too much, and the man
who is unjustly treated too little, of what is good. In the case of evil the
reverse is true; for the lesser evil is reckoned a good in comparison with the
greater evil, since the lesser evil is rather to be chosen than the greater,
and what is worthy of choice is good, and what is worthier of choice a greater
good.
This,
then, is one species of the just.
Chapter 4
(B) The remaining one is the rectificatory, which arises
in connexion with transactions both voluntary and involuntary. This form of the
just has a different specific character from the former. For the justice which
distributes common possessions is always in accordance with the kind of
proportion mentioned above (for in the case also in which the distribution is
made from the common funds of a partnership it will be according to the same
ratio which the funds put into the business by the partners bear to one
another); and the injustice opposed to this kind of justice is that which
violates the proportion. But the justice in transactions between man and man is
a sort of equality indeed, and the injustice a sort of inequality; not
according to that kind of proportion, however, but according to arithmetical proportion.
For it makes no difference whether a good man has defrauded a bad man or a bad
man a good one, nor whether it is a good or a bad man that has committed
adultery; the law looks only to the distinctive character of the injury, and
treats the parties as equal, if one is in the wrong and the other is being
wronged, and if one inflicted injury and the other has received it. Therefore,
this kind of injustice being an inequality, the judge tries to equalize it; for
in the case also in which one has received and the other has inflicted a wound,
or one has slain and the other been slain, the suffering and the action have
been unequally distributed; but the judge tries to equalize by means of the
penalty, taking away from the gain of the assailant. For the term ‘gain’ is
applied generally to such cases, even if it be not a term appropriate to
certain cases, e.g. to the person who inflicts a woundand ‘loss’ to the
sufferer; at all events when the suffering has been estimated, the one is
called loss and the other gain. Therefore the equal is intermediate between the
greater and the less, but the gain and the loss are respectively greater and
less in contrary ways; more of the good and less of the evil are gain, and the
contrary is loss; intermediate between them is, as we saw, equal, which we say
is just; therefore corrective justice will be the intermediate between loss and
gain. This is why, when people dispute, they take refuge in the judge; and to
go to the judge is to go to justice; for the nature of the judge is to be a
sort of animate justice; and they seek the judge as an intermediate, and in
some states they call judges mediators, on the assumption that if they get what
is intermediate they will get what is just. The just, then, is an intermediate,
since the judge is so. Now the judge restores equality; it is as though there
were a line divided into unequal parts, and he took away that by which the
greater segment exceeds the half, and added it to the smaller segment. And when
the whole has been equally divided, then they say they have ‘their own’ — i.e.
when they have got what is equal. The equal is intermediate between the greater
and the lesser line according to arithmetical proportion. It is for this reason
also that it is called just (sikaion), because it is a division into two equal
parts (sicha), just as if one were to call it sichaion; and the judge
(sikastes) is one who bisects (sichastes). For when something is subtracted
from one of two equals and added to the other, the other is in excess by these
two; since if what was taken from the one had not been added to the other, the
latter would have been in excess by one only. It therefore exceeds the
intermediate by one, and the intermediate exceeds by one that from which
something was taken. By this, then, we shall recognize both what we must
subtract from that which has more, and what we must add to that which has less;
we must add to the latter that by which the intermediate exceeds it, and
subtract from the greatest that by which it exceeds the intermediate. Let the
lines AA’, BB’, CC’ be equal to one another; from the line AA’ let the segment
AE have been subtracted, and to the line CC’ let the segment CD have been
added, so that the whole line DCC’ exceeds the line EA’ by the segment CD and
the segment CF; therefore it exceeds the line BB’ by the segment CD. (See
diagram.)
These names, both loss and gain, have come from voluntary exchange; for to have more than one’s own is called gaining, and to have less than one’s original share is called losing, e.g. in buying and selling and in all other matters in which the law has left people free to make their own terms; but when they get neither more nor less but just what belongs to themselves, they say that they have their own and that they neither lose nor gain.
Therefore the just is intermediate between a sort of
gain and a sort of loss, viz. those which are involuntary; it consists in
having an equal amount before and after the transaction.
Some
think that reciprocity is without qualification just, as the Pythagoreans said;
for they defined justice without qualification as reciprocity. Now
‘reciprocity’ fits neither distributive nor rectificatory justice — yet people
want even the justice of Rhadamanthus to mean this: “Should a man suffer what
he did, right justice would be done” — for in many cases reciprocity and
rectificatory justice are not in accord; e.g. if an official has inflicted a
wound, he should not be wounded in return, and if some one has wounded an
official, he ought not to be wounded only but punished in addition. Further
there is a great difference between a voluntary and an involuntary act. But in
associations for exchange this sort of justice does hold men together —
reciprocity in accordance with a proportion and not on the basis of precisely
equal return. For it is by proportionate requital that the city holds together.
Men seek to return either evil for evi — and if they cana not do so, think
their position mere slavery — or good for good — and if they cannot do so there
is no exchange, but it is by exchange that they hold together. This is why they
give a prominent place to the temple of the Graces — to promote the requital of
services; for this is characteristic of grace — we should serve in return one
who has shown grace to us, and should another time take the initiative in
showing it.
Now
proportionate return is secured by cross-conjunction. Let A be a
builder, B a shoemaker, C a house, D a shoe. The builder,
then, must get from the shoemaker the latter’s work, and must himself give him
in return his own. If, then, first there is proportionate equality of goods, and then
reciprocal action takes place, the result we mention will be effected. If not,
the bargain is not equal, and does not hold; for there is nothing to prevent
the work of the one being better than that of the other; they must therefore be
equated. (And this is true of the other arts also; for they would have been
destroyed if what the patient suffered had not been just what the agent did,
and of the same amount and kind.) For it is not two doctors that associate for
exchange, but a doctor and a farmer, or in general people who are different and
unequal; but these must be equated. This is why all things that are exchanged
must be somehow comparable. It is for this end that money has been introduced,
and it becomes in a sense an intermediate; for it measures all things, and
therefore the excess and the defect — how many shoes are equal to a house or to
a given amount of food. The number of shoes exchanged for a house (or for a
given amount of food) must therefore correspond to the ratio of builder to
shoemaker. For if this be not so, there will be no exchange and no intercourse.
And this proportion will not be effected unless the goods are somehow equal. All goods must therefore be
measured by some one thing, as we said before. Now this unit is in truth demand, which holds all
things together (for if men did not need one another’s goods at all, or did not need them equally,
there would be either no exchange or not the same exchange); but money has
become by convention a sort of representative of demand; and this is why it has the name ‘money’
(nomisma) — because it exists not by nature but by law (nomos) and it is in our
power to change it and make it useless. There will, then, be reciprocity when
the terms have been equated so that as farmer is to shoemaker, the amount of
the shoemaker’s work is to that of the farmer’s work for which it exchanges.
But we must not bring them into a figure of proportion when they have already
exchanged (otherwise one extreme will have both excesses), but when they still
have their own goods.
Thus they are equals and associates just because this equality can be effected
in their case. Let A be a farmer, C food, B a shoemaker, D
his product equated to C. If it had not been possible for reciprocity to
be thus effected, there would have been no association of the parties. That demand holds things
together as a single unit is shown by the fact that when men do not need one
another, i.e. when neither needs the other or one does not need the other, they
do not exchange, as we do when some one wants what one has oneself, e.g. when
people permit the exportation of corn in exchange for wine. This equation
therefore must be established. And for the future exchange — that if we do not
need a thing now we shall have it if ever we do need it — money is as it were
our surety; for it must be possible for us to get what we want by bringing the
money. Now the same thing happens to money itself as to goods — it is not always worth the same;
yet it tends to be steadier. This is why all goods must have a price set on them; for then there will always be
exchange, and if so, association of man with man. Money, then, acting as a
measure, makes goods
commensurate and equates them; for neither would there have been association if
there were not exchange, nor exchange if there were not equality, nor equality
if there were not commensurability. Now in truth it is impossible that things
differing so much should become commensurate, but with reference to demand they may become so
sufficiently. There must, then, be a unit, and that fixed by agreement (for
which reason it is called money); for it is this that makes all things
commensurate, since all things are measured by money. Let A be a house, B
ten minae, C a bed. A is half of B, if the house is worth
five minae or equal to them; the bed, C, is a tenth of B; it is
plain, then, how many beds are equal to a house, viz. five. That exchange took
place thus before there was money is plain; for it makes no difference whether
it is five beds that exchange for a house, or the money value of five beds.
We have now defined the unjust and the just. These having been marked off from each other, it is plain that just action is intermediate between acting unjustly and being unjustly treated; for the one is to have too much and the other to have too little. Justice is a kind of mean, but not in the same way as the other virtues, but because it relates to an intermediate amount, while injustice relates to the extremes. And justice is that in virtue of which the just man is said to be a doer, by choice, of that which is just, and one who will distribute either between himself and another or between two others not so as to give more of what is desirable to himself and less to his neighbour (and conversely with what is harmful), but so as to give what is equal in accordance with proportion; and similarly in distributing between two other persons. Injustice on the other hand is similarly related to the unjust, which is excess and defect, contrary to proportion, of the useful or hurtful. For which reason injustice is excess and defect, viz. Because it is productive of excess and defect — in one’s own case excess of what is in its own nature useful and defect of what is hurtful, while in the case of others it is as a whole like what it is in one’s own case, but proportion may be violated in either direction. In the unjust act to have too little is to be unjustly treated; to have too much is to act unjustly.
Let this be taken as our account of the
nature of justice and injustice, and similarly of the just and the unjust in
general.
__________________________